The number one trusted online resource for Catholic values
Menu
A+ A A-

Liberal Arts Education in a Free Society

  • JAMES V. SCHALL, S.J.

Liberal education agrees with Plato that self-rule is at the heart of civil order.


Schall1.JPG


Pompey now having ordered all things ... took his journey homewards.... When he came to Mitylene, he gave the city their freedom ... and was present at the contest, there periodically held, of poets.... He was extremely pleased with the theatre itself, and had a model of it taken, intending to erect one in Rome on the same design, but larger and more magnificent. When he came to Rhodes, he attended the lectures of all the philosophers there.... At Athens, also, he showed similar munificence to the philosophers, and gave fifty talents towards the repairing and beautifying of the city.... By all these acts he well hoped to return into Italy in the greatest splendour and glory possible to man, and find his family as desirous to see him as he felt himself to come home to them. But that supernatural agency, whose province and charge it is always to mix some ingredient of evil with the greatest and most glorious goods of fortune, had for some time back been busy in his own household, preparing him a sad welcome. For Mucia during his absence had dishonoured his bed....

Plutarch, The Life of Pompey. [1]

Im not absolutely certain of my facts, but I rather fancy its Shakespeare who says that its always just when a fellow is feeling particularly braced with things in general that Fate sneaks up behind him with the bit of lead piping. And what I driving at is that the man is perfectly right.

P. G. Wodehouse, Jeeves and the Unbidden Guest. [2] I

Human beings rightly puzzle about why their best-laid plans do not usually come to fruition. Perhaps, when thought about, they are still more puzzled when they consider a world, the actual world, in which at least some of their plans do work out well. How can this be? Human agency, after all, exists in a world in which it can subject at least some non-human things to its own purposes, in which it can persuade some human beings to follow its directions. Some correspondence evidently exists between the human mind and the things that are. Across rivers, gorges, and straits, we do build bridges that do not collapse. When we whistle to our dog, it comes running. We create neither the dog nor our ability to whistle nor the river, but we do invent the bridge. Thought arises from reality and reality is changed by our thought connected, as it is, to our hands and to the mouth we whistle with..

But we find an irony in our existence, as the two above-cited passages intimate. The greatest of political glory, in the case of the Roman General, is sorely tempered by the failure of moral virtue in his very home. He ended a war; he freed a city; he listened to philosophers; he beautified Athens; he planned a Roman theatre; he loved his family all recognized characteristics of a liberal and noble man. Yet, from the classic biographer of the ancient world to the great English humorist of the twentieth century, this precarious awareness of fallible human condition is simply present to educated men and to common folks alike.

What is called fate, properly considered, falls under divine providence wherein all things, even evil in its own way, work unto the good. Whether our propensity to find a touch of bad midst the most anticipated glories is attributed to a supernatural agency, with Plutarch, or, more amusingly, to the lead pipe of Fate with Wodehouse, or to providence in revelation, we cannot avoid the fact that we must account for a human condition that sees the good suffer and the wicked prosper. Still, this same human condition recognizes that oftentimes the good are indeed good and that evil is in fact firmly rejected. Such is our experience. II

The terms liberal education and free society arise out of the same source, out of the classic notion that we could and should first rule ourselves, that such rule is in our personal power. A free society meant one composed of those who in fact did rule themselves before they talked of ruling others. The rule of others is after the manner of the self-disciplined freedom found in those who are ruled. The word free in a free society does not refer to the capacity to do whatever we want, no matter what it is we want. The classic and pejorative definition of democracy arises from that undisciplined freedom or liberty that overlooks the importance of what it is we choose. Those sons of the Athenian citizens who left their parental homes without a capacity to rule themselves, as Aristotle tells us at the very end of his Ethics, required a political power of coercion to contain this inner disorder so that it would not unjustly injure others. Thus, freedom is first an inner willingness and an acquired habit whereby we rule ourselves. It does not refer to doing whatever we want but to doing what is right, worthy, and noble.

We also need to rule ourselves for some purpose. Pirates, robbers, and rakes are often disciplined in their own way to enable them to achieve, with a certain skill, something unworthy of man. Thus, it is possible for us to rule ourselves either for a wicked purpose or for a noble one, knowing quite well the difference between the one and the other. Moreover, it is difficult to see what a noble purpose might be if we are not first properly guided and habituated. This capacity to rule ourselves takes more than just knowledge; it requires effort, choice, experience, repetition of acts. The severest penalty for not ruling ourselves consists in nothing less than being unfree, being unable even to see the highest things because we are too busy guiding ourselves to purposes that are unworthy. All public disorders, and hence all unfreedom and moral slavery, are rooted in personal disorders, in wills and in choices. Not knowing the important things is mostly a question of not willing to rule ourselves. The first notion of liberal then is that of ruling ourselves, of knowing what purposes for which we rule ourselves are good and which are not, of disciplining ourselves in single acts actually to make good choices. III

A second meaning of the word liberal has to do with property and how we stand towards what we own. Aristotle called the virtue by which we ruled over our material goods liberality or generosity. Liberality is a surprisingly important virtue as it applies to everyone, rich and poor alike in the case of the rich, it is called munificence. One of the purposes we can choose as the principle of ruling ourselves, one of the definitions we can give ourselves of our own happiness, is precisely wealth and wealth-getting. We can use wealth wrongly or rightly, but wealth itself is a good. It is worth causing to exist by our knowledge, inventiveness, and labor.

The fact that we need some material goods or wealth to live at all is simply a fact. Moreover, we ought not give away what is not ours. Private property is in general the best way to own and care for our material possessions. Furthermore, we reveal our souls to others by how we stand to our own wealth, however great or small it be, by how we use it. Society and personal relationships ought, then, to be a complexus of exchanges of justice and liberality, of things owed and of things freely given and received whereby we see the good of others and respond to it with our goods. To a society wherein everything is provided by public ownership and distribution, wherein nothing can be liberally given and only rights exist, we prefer one wherein most things are taken care of by ourselves, by our own virtues and our own property. IV

A third meaning of the word liberal, its most profound meaning, has to do with knowing, knowing things for their own sakes. The Scripture says that it is the truth that will make us free. We do not make truth, but we acknowledge it, affirm of what is that it is and of what is not, that it is not, as Plato said. We live in a time that is antagonistic to truth, that thinks that the truth is what makes us unfree. Our society is enslaved by a freedom that does not acknowledge the truth that frees it. The false notion of freedom is that we will not be bound by anything that is, including our own being. We must, it is said, transcend, be free of, all order or reality that we do not cause. We lust after a kind of diabolic freedom that binds us to nothing but ourselves.

The free man in his actions is what Aristotle called, a cause of himself. But this does not mean that such a free man made the things that are. He is free when he knows. The very purpose of his mind is to become what he is not. His freedom consists in his capacity to know what is without being distracted by urgings of use or of pleasure or of power. Our highest power or faculty is to know, to know the truth of things. No society or individual can be safe if it does not possess those who are free to pursue the truth apart from political or economic coercion or opinion.

The political order and the economic order exist to make this freedom possible; they are not themselves the highest things and can be its greatest hindrances. Civil and political liberties are themselves means, not ends. Even institutions designed to foster truth in freedom can become corrupt or misguided. Universities, media, religion, or other voluntary societies can impose conditions that make the freedom to know the truth dangerous or difficult.

Properly speaking, liberal education includes all three forms of freedom: 1) the freedom that comes when we rule ourselves, rule for a proper good the tendencies we are given in nature; 2) the freedom that comes when we use our goods and property liberally and generously for a human purpose, including our own independence and dignity, when we can give and receive, when we show our souls to be free, and 3) the freedom to know the truth, to have the time and space in which we can know and see things for their own sakes, when we are not deflected by our own desires or by utilitarian, pleasurable, or political purposes. V

Oftentimes we talk as if education alone will make us free or as if it is the principal element in our freedom. In a famous debate between Aristotle and Plato, it was Aristotle who pointed out that the possession or definition of knowledge does not assure us of virtue or its exercise. On the other hand, virtue, even if we acquire it, is not itself its own reward but is always directed to something besides itself. Ultimately, it is directed to the truth of being in which our happiness exists. Liberal education in a free society always needs first to be seen in the light of virtue, of the will to rule ourselves for a worthy purpose. We are not free if we simply do whatever we want to do, whatever it is. Doing precisely whatever we want is indeed a form of slavery to our own desires or passions. Freedom in democracies often does tend to this uncontrolled notion of freedom wherein any claim that our wants or our purposes be limited or directed, even by ourselves, is looked upon as contrary to freedom.

Plato is famous for pointing out the relation between the order or disorder of our souls and the order or disorder of our societies. Machiavelli is rather infamous for the contrary idea that we must allow the prince to do either good or evil for him to be successful, that we must lower our sights because we cannot expect men to be virtuous. Rousseau instructed us that virtue and vice are products not of our wills or habits but of society and its institutions. Virtue results not of our own efforts to rule ourselves but of some institution that takes rule out of the self and places it in external law or will.

Liberal education agrees with Plato that self-rule is at the heart of civil order. It rejects Machiavellis indifference to the distinction of good and evil and fears Rousseaus placing of virtue and vice in the hands of the state and its defining and coercive powers. St. Thomas said, that, as a practical rule, we should not expect more virtue than can be found in the generality of men in any society. Still, he thought, we need to know what virtue is, even when we do not practice it. The role of liberal education in a free society is precisely to keep these three ideas of freedom alive among us: the idea 1) that we can rule ourselves, 2) that we can be generous with our property, and 3) that we can know the truth that alone makes us free and is the purpose for which we seek to know at all.

That there is some evil mixed with the most glorious deeds, that when our lives are particularly braced in general, we are likely to be lead piped, these are experiences common to our kind, the knowledge and meaning of which are essential to our physical and spiritual well-being. The liberal education that does not have a proper appreciation of moral evil and of the likelihood of accident in our lot ill prepares us for our world. But the essential purpose of liberal education is precisely to enable us to be free to rule, to give, and to know to rule ourselves, to give from our abundance to others, and to know what is the truth of things, the truth of human things and, in so far as we can, of divine things.

ENDNOTES

  1. Plutarch, "The Life of Pompey," Plutarch: The Lives of the Noble Grecians and Romans, trans. John Dryden, rev. Arthur Hugh Clough (New York: The Modern Library, n.d.), 770. Back to text.
  2. P. G. Wodehouse, The World of Jeeves (New York: Manor Books, 1974), 138. Back to text.

This is Meaghen Gonzalez, Editor of CERC. I hope you appreciated this piece. We curate these articles especially for believers like you.

Please show your appreciation by making a $3 donation. CERC is entirely reader supported.

dividertop

Acknowledgement

Schall, S. J., James V. Liberal Arts Education in a Free Society, in Religion & Liberty, 8 (July/August, 1998), 5-7.

Reprinted with permission of Rev. James V. Schall, S.J.,

The Author

Schall3schall91James V. Schall, S.J. 1928-2019, who served as a professor at Georgetown University for thirty-five years, was one of the most prolific Catholic writers in America. Among his many books are A Line Through the Human Heart: On Sinning and Being ForgivenOn Islam: A Chronological Record, 2002-2018, Reasonable Pleasures: The Strange Coherences of Catholicism, The Mind That Is Catholic: Philosophical & Political Essays, On the Unseriousness of Human Affairs: Teaching, Writing, Playing, Believing, Lecturing, Philosophizing, Singing, Dancing; Roman Catholic Political Philosophy; The Order of Things; The Life of the Mind: On the Joys and Travails of Thinking; Another Sort of Learning, Sum Total Of Human Happiness, and A Student's Guide to Liberal Learning.

Copyright © 1988 James V. Schall, S.J.

Subscribe to our Weekly Update

* indicates required